Phonetically Driven Phonology: The Role of Optimality Theory and Inductive Grounding
نویسنده
چکیده
Functionalist phonetic literature has shown how the phonologies of human languages are arranged to facilitate ease of articulation and perception. The explanatory force of phonological theory is greatly increased if it can directly access these research results. There are two formal mechanisms that together can facilitate the link-up of formal to functional work. As others have noted, Optimality Theory, with its emphasis on directly incorporating principles of markedness, can serve as part of the bridge. Another mechanism is proposed here: an algorithm for inductive grounding permits the language learner to access the knowledge gained from experience in articulation and perception, and form from it the appropriate set of formal phonological constraints. Phonetically-Driven Phonology p. 2 1. Phonological Functionalism The difference between formalist and functionalist approaches in linguistics has taken different forms in different areas. For phonology, and particularly for the study of fullyproductive sound patterns, the functionalist approach has traditionally been phonetic in character. For some time, work in the phonetic literature, such as Ohala (1974, 1978, 1981, 1983), Ohala and Ohala (1993), Liljencrants and Lindblom (1972), Lindblom (1983, 1990), and Westbury and Keating (1986), has argued that the sound patterns of languages are effectively arranged to facilitate ease of articulation and distinctness of contrasting forms in perception. In this view, much of the patterning of phonology reflects principles of good design. In contemporary phonological theorizing, such a view has not been widely adopted. Phonology has been modeled as a formal system, set up to mirror the characteristic phonological behavior of languages. Occasionally, scholars have made a nod towards the phonetic sensibleness of a particular proposal. But on the whole, the divide between formal and functionalist approaches in phonology has been as deep as anywhere else in the study of language. It would be pointless (albeit fun) to discuss reasons for this based on the sociology of the fields of phonetics and phonology. More pertinently, I will claim that part of the problem has been that phonological theory has not until recently advanced to the point where a serious coming to grips with phonetic functionalism would be workable. 2. Optimality Theory The novel approach to linguistic theorizing known as Optimality Theory (Prince and Smolensky 1993) appears to offer the prospect of a major change in this situation. Here are some of the basic premises of the theory as I construe it. First, phonological grammar is not arranged in the manner of Chomsky and Halle (1968), in essence as an assembly line converting underlying to surface representations in a series of steps. Instead, the phonology selects an output form from the set of logical possibilities. It makes its selection using a large set of constraints, which specify what is “good” about an output, in the following two ways: (1) a. Phonotactics: “The output should have phonological property X.” b. Faithfulness: “The output should resemble the input in possessing property Y.” Phonotactic constraints express properties of phonological markedness, which are typically uncontroversial. For example, they require that syllables be open, or that front vowels be unrounded, and so on. The Faithfulness constraints embody a detailed factorization of what it means for the output to resemble the input; they are fully satisfied when the output is identical to the input. Phonetically-Driven Phonology p. 3 Constraints can conflict with each other. Often, it is impossible for the output to have the desired phonotactic properties and also be faithful to the input; or for two different phonotactic constraints to be satisfied simultaneously. Therefore, all constraints are prioritized; that is, ranked. Prioritization drives a specific winnowing process (not described here) that ultimately selects the output of the grammar from the set of logical possibilities by ruling out all but a single winner. I will take the general line that Optimality Theory is a good thing. First, it shares the virtues of other formal theories: when well implemented, such theories provide falsifiability, so that the errors in an analysis can lead to improvement or replacement. Further, formal theories characteristically increase the pattern recognition capacity of the analyst. For example, it was only when the formal theory of moras was introduced (Hyman 1985) that it became clear that compensatory phonological processes always conserve mora count (see Hyman, and for elaboration Hayes 1989). Second, Optimality Theory has permitted solutions to problems that simply were not treatable in earlier theories. Examples are the metrical phonology of Guugu Yimidhirr (Kager, to appear), or the long-standing ordering paradoxes involving phonology and reduplication (McCarthy and Prince 1995). Most crucially, Optimality Theory has the advantage of allowing us to incorporate general principles of markedness into language-specific analyses. Previously, a formal phonology consisted of a set of somewhat arbitrary-looking rules. The analyst could only look at the rules “from the outside” and determine how they reflect general principles of markedness (or at best, supplement the rules with additional markedness principles, as in Chomsky and Halle (1968, Ch. 9), Schachter (1969), or Chen (1973)). Under Optimality Theory, the principles of markedness (stated explicitly and ranked) form the sole ingredients of the language-specific analysis. The mechanism of selection by ranked constraints turns out to be such an amazingly powerful device that it can do all the rest. Since rankings are the only arbitrary element in the system, the principled character of language-specific analyses is greatly increased. This is necessarily an argument by assertion, but I believe a fair comparison of the many phonological analyses of the same material in both frameworks would support it. 3. What is a Principled Constraint? The question of what makes a constraint “principled” is one that may be debated. The currently most popular answer, I think, relies on typological evidence: a principled constraint is one that “does work” in many languages, and does it in different ways. But there is another answer to the question of what makes a constraint principled: a constraint can be justified on functional grounds. In the case of phonetic functionalism, a well-motivated phonological constraint would be one that either renders speech easier to articulate or renders contrasting forms easier to distinguish perceptually. From the Phonetically-Driven Phonology p. 4 functionalist point of view, such constraints are a priori plausible, under the reasonable hypothesis that language is a biological system that is designed to perform its job well and efficiently. Optimality Theory thus presents a new and important opportunity to phonological theorists. Given that the theory thrives on principled constraints, and given that functionally motivated phonetic constraints are inherently principled, the clear route to take is to explore how much of phonology can be constructed on this basis. One might call such an approach “phonetically-driven Optimality-theoretic phonology.” A theory of this kind would help close the long-standing and regrettable gap between phonology and phonetics. 4. Research in Phonetically-Driven Optimality-Theoretic Phonology The position just taken regarding phonetics and Optimality Theory is not original with me, but is inspired by ongoing research, much of inspired by Donca Steriade, which attempts to make use of OT to produce phonetically-driven formal accounts of various phonological phenomena. For instance, Steriade (1993, 1997) considers the very basic question of segmental phonotactics in phonology: what segments are allowed to occur where? Her perspective is a novel one, taking the line that perception is the dominant factor. Roughly speaking, Steriade suggests that segments preferentially occur where they can best be heard. The crucial part is that many segments (for example, voiceless stops) are rendered audible largely or entirely by the contextual acoustic cues that they engender on neighboring segments through coarticulation. In such a situation, it is clearly to the advantage of particular languages to place strong restrictions on the phonological locations of such segments. Following this approach, and incorporating a number of results from research in speech perception, Steriade is able to reconstruct the traditional typology of “segment licensing,” including what was previously imagined to be an across-the-board preference for consonants to occur in syllable onset position. She goes on to show that there in fact are areas where this putative preference fails as an account of segmental phonotactics: one example is the preference for retroflexes to occur postvocalically (in either onset or coda); preglottalized sonorants work similarly. As Steriade shows, these otherwisebaffling cases have specific explanations, based on the peculiar acoustics of the segments involved. She then makes use of Optimality Theory to develop explicit formal analyses of the relevant cases. Phonetically-driven approaches similar to Steriade’s have lead to progress in the understanding of various other areas of phonology: place assimilation (Jun 1995a,b; Myers, this volume), vowel harmony (Archangeli and Pulleyblank 1994, Kaun 1995a,b), vowel-consonant interactions (Flemming 1995), syllable weight (Gordon, 1997), laryngeal Phonetically-Driven Phonology p. 5 features for vowels (Silverman 1995), non-local assimilation (Gafos 1996), and lenition (Kirchner, in progress).
منابع مشابه
Logical and Substantive Scales in Phonology
This study addresses two assumptions that have accompanied generative phonology from its inception, namely the binarity and phonetic grounding of features. It argues, based on both theoretical and empirical grounds, for the existence of n-ary phonological relationships that are not necessarily grounded in a phonetic dimension or parameter. It presents, further, a model labelled Structural Optim...
متن کاملPhonetically Driven Phonology: The Role of OT and Inductive Grounding
Functionalist phonetic literature has shown how the phonologies of human languages are arranged to facilitate ease of articulation and perception. The explanatory force of phonological theory is greatly increased if it can directly access these research results. There are two formal mechanisms that together can facilitate the link-up of formal to functional work. As others have noted, Optimalit...
متن کاملOptionality and Gradience in Persian Phonology: An Optimality Treatment
The distribution of the allophones of /?/in certain contexts involves free variation and gradient preferences. An organized survey was conducted to elicit the judgments of 37 native Persian speakers concerning the well-formedness of /?/allophonic behavior in five different phonological positions. The results showed that the differences in judgment between the various categories are not just t...
متن کاملOn the Naturalness of Unnatural Rules
In the 1970’s the approach of Natural Phonology focused on the observation that phonetically motivated (“natural”) processes are common in the phonologies of the world’s languages, while phonetically unmotivated (“unnatural”) ones are uncommon (cf. Stampe 1969, Vennemann 1974, Hooper 1976, Donegan and Stampe 1979; for reactions at the time see, for example, Hellberg 1978 and Anderson 1981). Muc...
متن کاملWhat should phonology explain ?
A standard observation about the phonological patterns found in the world's languages, and a standard explanation of this observation: (1) Phonetically motivated (" natural ") processes are common in the phonologies of the world's languages, while phonetically unmotivated (" unnatural ") ones are uncommon. (2) The causes of phonological patterns are represented in the mental grammar. A phonolog...
متن کامل